Philip Badger
So far in this series, I’ve showcased the writers Ruth Loten, Jane Langan, BeckCollett, Ron Hardwick, L.N.Hunter, Katherine Blessan, Jill Saudek, Colin Johnson, Sue Davnall, Alain Li Wan Po and Lily Lawson. You can find all these showcases by scrolling back through the material on this blog.
Our second showcase of 2024 turns the spotlight onto writer and teacher Philip Badger. Unlike many of the writers who have been showcased here, Philip is not a writer of fiction but a commentator on life - he writes articles which incorporate philosophy, sociology, economics, politics and psychology, many of which have been published in magazines such as Philosophy Now. During the first lockdown in 2020, he wrote a complete book presenting his thoughts on how we might change as a society into a better, kinder nation.
Biography
Phil Badger was born in an industrial town in the north of England. He had all the usual childhood traumas and vividly recalls standing in the cloakroom of his primary school and thinking about how unfair the world was. Unlike most kids he took the extra step of wondering what a fair world would look like. In retrospect, this was the beginning of his relationship with difficult questions.
However, his early academic life was somewhat blighted by dyslexia and he didn’t read before he was ten. Phil went on to study Social Sciences and Philosophy at North Staffordshire Polytechnic. After acquiring a few more qualifications, he trained as a teacher and still teaches A level students in semi-retirement.
From the early 2000s onwards, he’s been a regular contributor to Philosophy Now Magazine and has also featured in that publication’s anthologies of key articles.
He met his wife, who hails from the same home town, when they were both teaching in London but, as he says, ‘it would be extraordinary if coincidences didn’t happen’.
******
Philip has chosen to showcase one of his most well-known articles which examines the famous thought-experiment popularly known as 'The Trolley Problem'. This article first appeared in the Sep/October edition of Philosophy Now in 2011.
How To Get Off Our Trolleys
Phil Badger tackles the famous
‘Trolley Problem’ of ethics.
So-called ‘Trolley Problems’, in
which we are confronted by tortuously difficult ethical dilemmas, have become
part of the stock-in-trade of moral philosophy over the last few years. The
basic scenario, which can be endlessly tweaked to provoke ever more rigorous
examination of our moral reasoning, concerns a run-away trolley on an imaginary
railway line. The trolley is on a lethal collision course with an oblivious
group of (say, five) workmen, but can potentially be diverted onto another
track by your pulling on a conveniently-placed lever. The problem is that this
will place the trolley on a different, equally lethal collision course with an
innocent individual.
Readers who haven’t come across
this thought-experiment before might pause for a moment to consider what they
might do. Some of you will undoubtedly be in favour of hauling on the lever and
consigning the poor innocent singleton to oblivion. We can certainly understand
why some people might be minded to do so. In the situation presented there
seems a clear choice between allowing the deaths of a group of people, and
acting to end the life of one. For them the ‘best’ option – meaning the one
that will cause the least suffering – is to favour the many. For others the
story will not be so simple, and they will draw a distinction between ‘killing’
one individual by active intervention and ‘letting several die’ by remaining
passive. This is a distinction we’ll return to later.
Problems With Morality
What we have in this thought-experiment
is a place to start thinking about our instinctive moral responses (what
philosophers call our ‘moral intuitions’) and the way that these intuitions may
or may not cohere together or be capable of any kind of rational justification.
For a so-called ‘act utilitarian’
like Jeremy Bentham (1784-1832), the measure of the moral validity of any
particular act is the extent to which it promotes pleasure/benefit and
minimises pain/suffering. For Bentham our trolley problem would be a ‘no brainer’:
levers would be pulled and our lone protagonist squashed without regret. But an
unequivocal utilitarian would be a colder fish than most of us might want to
spend any time with. Perhaps one of Mr Spock’s fully Vulcan friends might be an
unperturbed ‘trolley diverter’; but the rest of us would be in for a lot of bad
dreams. The ‘lever puller’ would deserve our utmost sympathy and support (even
if we disagreed with her decision) precisely because we would empathise both
with her momentary dilemma and her subsequent anguish.
What this tells us depends on our
philosophical perspective. Presumably, Bentham would bemoan our lily-livered
sentimentality and remind us of the superior rationality of the utilitarian
case. Someone had to die, and it is better, in this case, that it should be
some one and
not a whole group. Of course this highlights the problem of what we might call
the essential ‘relativism’ of the utilitarian position: any act might be
permitted and a similar act be prohibited depending on the circumstances.
Sometimes it will be acceptable to squash the individual, and sometimes the
group (imagine that we recognise the lone individual as a world famous surgeon
whom we anticipate will go on to save and improve many lives). Of course,
making morality relative to the consequences of actions is, on another level, a
morally absolute principle (we must always act
to maximise ‘utility’). But this is a principle that most of us find deeply
disturbing for the following reason.
Imagine applying our trolley logic
to the case of the death penalty. Imagine further that a new study showed that,
without question, the death penalty really does cut down the number of murders
committed in any given year. Surely, under such (admittedly hypothetical)
circumstances, the lever diverting the trolley would be rapidly replaced by the
lever operating the executioner’s trapdoor. In fact, the replacement is made
easier when we consider that the ‘sacrificed’ individual is likely to be a
cold-blooded murderer. The wrinkle here is the word ‘likely’, because, from a
purely utilitarian perspective, the occasional execution of an innocent makes
no difference to the morality of the death penalty – the net benefit justifies
the sacrifice.
At this point some readers might be
feeling a little uneasy because they can feel that no slope is slipperier than
the one we’re now on. So let’s say that it turns out that executing the family
of a murderer is even more likely to produce a net reduction in pain and
suffering – perhaps the deterrence effect is so strong that we only need to
wipe out one family per year to guarantee a violence-free life for the rest of
us.
Or, imagine a further series of
trolley-like situations. Firstly, a terrorist group hijacks an airliner and
demands that David Cameron be handed over to them for ‘revolutionary justice’.
If we do not comply with their demands, they will blow up the airliner and all
on board. We might construct a utilitarian argument for not giving in to the
terrorists on the grounds that doing so will encourage further outrages of the
same kind; but is this the only moral reason not to drag Mr Cameron to his
death? Most of us would think not.
Take another situation: a variation
on the classic ‘ticking bomb’ problem, in which we are invited to consider the
morality of using torture to help discover the location of a device primed to
explode with devastating effects on the lives of hundreds or even thousands. We
might be sympathetic to the desperation of the field officer who reluctantly
gets out his pliers; but what if, to extract the necessary information, they
end up being employed on the terrorist’s five-year-old child?
We can’t dodge the ethical issue by
claiming that torture doesn’t work, any more than we could by arguing that the
death penalty is not an effective deterrent. The point of such
thought-experiments is to face up to how utilitarian we actually would be prepared
to be when the ‘utility’ of an act is not in question. Does there come a point
where we must say that some actions, such as the torture of children, are
always wrong, no matter what the net benefit to others may be?
However, again, the answer is not
obvious. The problem with the ‘morally absolute’ position is two-fold. Firstly,
the consistent utilitarian might insist that we be clear what our limits are to
how much avoidable suffering are we prepared to allow in order to keep our
hands clean: do we waver when the stakes are sufficiently high? Let’s say
torturing the child saves 100,000 lives. Does that make a difference? How about
a million? Secondly, what kinds of act do we decide to be beyond the pale?
Shall we reply that morality has nothing to do with consequences, or should we try to find a way in which the consequences can be given a weight, but only so far that they don’t lead to ‘unacceptable’ places? The first position is associated with Kant, and leads to some very odd moral conclusions.
Can & Kant
For Kant, morality was a matter of
‘categorical imperatives’, which are best understood as absolute rules which
could be generated by the use of reason by any morally-competent individual.
Kant gives three formulations of the categorical imperative which are
superficially dissimilar but which turn out to be equivalent. There isn’t space
here to do anything like justice to any of the formulations; but, to begin
with, we’ll consider his idea that we
should only act in such a way as we would will the principle (his
word is ‘maxim’) of our
action to be a universal law. In other words, we should act only in
ways that we would want others to act in similar circumstances.
It is notoriously easy to misread
Kant as arguing that the consequences of our actions are what matters in
judging their moral rectitude. If we say, as Kant says, that we should only act
in ways we wouldn’t mind other people acting, it looks pretty much as if we’re
asking ‘what would the consequences be if everyone acted that way?’ But as
Michael Sandel has pointed out in Justice (2009),
this is not what Kant is saying. In fact, Kant thinks that we need to act
towards others in a way that respects what it is in them that I demand is
respected by them in me – my capacity for autonomous (self-governing) action.
What’s wrong with stealing is not that the world would descend into chaos if
everyone did it (this would be a ‘rule utilitarian’ argument), but that in
stealing I act without respect for the autonomy of the person I steal from, and
so imply that no one’s autonomy matters.
Kant’s view of morality is hugely
demanding, and in the words of another of his formulations, asks us to ‘treat
others as not a means to an end but as an end in themselves’. Thus for
Kantians, utilitarian calculations about the benefits of sacrificing David
Cameron, executing the innocent or pulling ‘trolley diverting’ levers are not
to be entertained. On this deontological (duty-based)
perspective, some things are absolute wrongs.
This position might make us all
feel a lot more comfortable than the utilitarian nightmare described earlier;
but once again, things are not so easy, because in severing the connection
between the morality of an act and its consequences, Kant commits himself to a
position many of us find just as difficult.
Famously, Kant argues that to lie
is an absolute wrong – how can we respect the autonomy of others if we
intentionally deprive them of the truth? This sounds fine until we run into
what I’ll call ‘the case of the hidden Jews’. Imagine that you’re hiding a
family of Jewish people from the Nazis, and that you have an SS officer at the
door asking you if you’ve seen them. Kant does some famous wriggling about such
issues, in that he suggests that we’re allowed to fail to give the information
(we might tell the SS officer that “there were Jews about at some point in the
past”) but not to lie. But this is not very convincing: we all want to say that
the moral thing is to lie in the most convincing way possible to save them. In
other words, in this and equivalent cases, the terrible consequences of not
lying are more important than any abstract principle [see also here].
Attempts at Reconciliation
To say I’ve oversimplified things
here might be a bit of an understatement, but the point remains that our ‘moral
intuitions’ – our gut instincts – evidently pull us in two directions. At times
it seems right that we aim to minimise suffering in a utilitarian style, while,
at others, we want to be deontologists (absolutely principled) like Kant. The
big question is, can the two positions be coherently reconciled?
If we think a bit more about our
David Cameron example, we might get a clue about how to make a start in this
direction. One response would be to argue that the terrorists who hijack the
plane and threaten to blow it up are responsible, so the terrible consequences
of not complying with their demands should not weigh on our consciences. This
position, proposed by the neo-Kantian Alan Gewirth in Reason and Morality, (1980),
is plausible, but not altogether helpful. One problem with it is that it does
not apply to situations in which we cannot blame someone else for our actions.
We might suppose that we could try to blame the terrorist for the agonies of
his tortured child in the ‘ticking bomb’ case; but very few will be much
convinced by this move. Similarly, if we pull the lever in our initial trolley
scenario, there can be no doubt that we have chosen to do something and that
responsibility rests with us. The same logic applies, for example, to the use
of deadly force against civilian populations in war time. Dropping atom bombs
might seem justified on grounds of utility – to curtail even more extensive
suffering by ending the war – but not on the grounds that the leaders of the
other side made us do it.
Another try would be to distinguish
between ‘acts’ and ‘omissions’, such that we see ourselves as responsible for
the former but not the latter. The most usual employment of this distinction is
in distinguishing between ‘killing’ and ‘letting die’ in the case of gravely
ill patients nearing the end of life. ‘Killing’ would involve administering
drugs to terminate the patient’s life in order to end their suffering, while
‘letting die’ might involve the withholding of treatment in order to hasten
death. The problem here is that doing nothing might cause significant amounts
of suffering in its own right. Not hydrating or feeding a patient (or not
pulling the lever to divert the trolley) might cause more suffering than active
intervention. (This is one reason why many philosophers share my sense that the
distinction between acts and omissions is inherently dubious.)
Thirdly, we can invoke the so
called ‘principle of double effect’, which suggests that we can’t be held
responsible for the unintended or secondary effects of particular actions. A
terminally ill patient may be given large doses of morphine to alleviate pain,
and this might also, incidentally, hasten his death. Or perhaps a leader might
believe he can bring an end to some period of terrible human suffering by, for
instance, dropping an atomic bomb on a Japanese city. In this case his
principle goal is not to kill the maximum number of non-combatants, but rather
to save lives in the long run. Similarly, when we pull the lever to divert the
trolley, we do not intend the death of the hapless individual who is now in its
path, but rather to save the lives of the group who now aren’t. Yet the trolley
example is not quite analogous to the atomic bomb scenario, and we have to
invoke a famous refinement to make it so. Imagine that we can only save the
group by pushing an fat individual into the trolley’s path. Now we have
to will the
death of the fat man to bring about our goal. This surely feels closer to the
situation of nuclear attack that President Truman must have agonised over
(ironically, one of the bombs dropped on Japan was codenamed ‘fat man’). Yet by
the same logic, we have to acknowledge that killing the innocents is not just
a side effect of
dropping the bomb, so the principle of double effect does not apply.
Freedom and Sacrifice
Again, we have to face the
competing demands of powerful and intuitively plausible understandings of
morality. Some things seem wrong no matter what the supposed benefits might be.
Torturing children to extract information from the enemy seems to fall under
this heading: the ends don’t justify the means. However, the sacrifice of the
few for the many is difficult to resist. So if the trolley or the bomb or the
hangman’s rope kills a few innocents and saves many, what are we to do? It is
easy to be an absolutist when you don’t have Truman’s job, and a true
utilitarian will tell us we are just being self-indulgent when we entertain our
moral qualms anyway.
At this point let’s consider the
psychology of the situation. Firstly, few of us would object to the notion of
individual sacrifice when such sacrifice is voluntary. Imagine the fat man
hurling himself in the path of the trolley, or Mr Cameron stoically arriving at
the airport and, unimpressed by our pleas, handing himself over to the
terrorists to face his fate. Under these circumstances, the horror of using a
person as a means to an end is transformed to awe at an act of human nobility.
Being the beneficiary of such an act would be a huge burden, but less so t han
being the beneficiary of the death of an unwilling and terrified individual.
This acknowledges our natural revulsion to the horrific injustice perpetrated
upon the involuntary sacrifices.
So, where does all this leave us?
Can we give a plausible account of morality which takes into consideration both
the sense that we have to weigh the consequences of our actions and also the
sense that, nonetheless, there are moments when consequences are secondary to
higher principles? Perhaps we can, but only at a great cost, which includes
substituting Kant’s notion of ‘autonomy’ for a sense of autonomy we’ll find
more familiar.
The first point is that autonomy,
in the sense of my ability to choose my actions uncoerced by others, doesn’t
always matter to us. My freedom is limited by many laws, and yet I don’t feel
conspicuously ‘un-free’. In some countries I’ll be fined for crossing a road on
a red light, but that doesn’t make me ‘un-free’. What matters supremely is that
those things about which I get to make choices are the ones which make life
meaningful to me (this is the more familiar, non-Kantian sense of ‘autonomy’).
The law doesn’t prescribe my values or my deepest commitments, nor should it.
My big life choices must remain matters of non-interference, because robbing me
of these things would render my life meaningless to me. Thus, on neo-Kantian
grounds, I have to will the same respect for what I call ‘the large-scale
concepts of the good’ of others. On this basis, nobody can be handed over to
terrorists against their will, unjustly hung, or thrown in front of a runaway
trolley. (Although, i n the case of our initial trolley scenario, since there
is no possibility of consulting any of the potential victims about what they
would choose to do, we might argue that their autonomy becomes irrelevant to
the situation and utilitarian considerations become primary. Thus it is right to
pull the lever and save the many. We might even decide to ascribe heroic status
to the lone victim – after all, she might have decided to sacrifice herself.
This is certainly more likely than the whole group of people on the other track
doing so for her.)
At this point we might be feeling a
little smug because we have, apparently, rendered two plausible but apparently
conflicting moral principles compatible. However, I mentioned earlier that
there was a cost to my strategy. In making the holding of personal large-scale
concepts of the good a criteria for moral status, I’ve opened up two
unpalatable possibilities. Firstly, that beings who have no capacity for
holding such concepts must be accounted to be morally inferior – which might
sound okay until you realise that small children, the mentally ill, the
intellectually impaired and animals all come into this category. Secondly, if,
for ‘morally immature’ beings, we then make the capacity to suffer the only applicable
criteria for their moral consideration, there are no ethical grounds for
favouring infant or mentally challenged humans over many other creatures. For
some philosophers, such as Peter Singer (Practical
Ethics, 1979), this moral equality with animals is not much of a
problem – but for others it certainly will be. You might also point out that I
seem to have committed myself to the position that a comatose fat man can be
dropped onto the tracks without a quibble (we can’t consult him on his
large-scale concept of the good, and he’s likely to suffer far less than the
fully conscious guy who’ll get quashed if we pull our original lever).
Perhaps, in the end, we have to
invoke the collective ‘large-scale concept of the good of society’ (or even
humanity) to resolve these remaining issues. Perhaps, to use Rawls’ phrase, we
can rely on an ‘overlapping consensus’ about values in society’s concept of
large-scale good: no decent human being would want to be saved by information
acquired by the torture of a child. Perhaps; but there seems some serious
question-begging going on at this point about what’s decent. Yet my hope is
that a social consensus on non-negotiable goods is the result of the kind of
discussion we’ve been engaged in, rather than being a fairly implausible
foundation for it. This is a place to start a conversation and not to end it.
© Phil Badger 2011
Phil Badger teaches philosophy and psychology in Sheffield. He would like to thank Tony Cole for provoking him into writing this article
And finally we come to The Big
Interview, in which Philip kindly answers
writing-related questions and lets us
into some of his writing secrets...
How old were you when you first knew you wanted to be a writer, and what set you off down that journey?
I knew I wanted to write something from a very early age but this was a
bit paradoxical considering that I was a dyslexic kid who couldn’t read until I
was ten! Academic writing obviously came later.
Tell us about the
books and writers that have shaped your life and your writing career.
That’s quite a difficult one. The first book that really grabbed me as
far as the quality of the writing was concerned was J. S. Mill’s ‘On liberty’.
This is a book of philosophy written in with a kind of luminous beauty. I have
to say that some of Wittgenstein’s writing is also stunningly good but, in
terms of the impact on my own thinking, I’d say that the American Philosopher
John Rawls has the biggest influence. I’d make a bigger claim. In fact – I’d
say Rawls was the most important philosopher of the twentieth century.
Have your children,
other family members, friends or teachers inspired any of your writing?
I first studied philosophy at North Staffordshire Polytechnic in the
1980s under the guidance of a lecturer called Peter Shott. Pete was’ and still is,
a remarkably bright man and a charismatic teacher. I’ve also been lucky to have
a wealth of thoughtful and articulate colleagues during my career who have
stimulated my thinking in all kinds of ways.
Does the place you
live now, or have lived in the past, have any impact on your writing?
There is a tradition in philosophy which denies the significance of
place in our thought. Socrates is said to have claimed the he was a ‘citizen of
the world’ rather than of Athens (although there is some thought that this is
mis-attributed). The thing is that lots of people who write philosophy aspire
to produce work which has a kind of ‘universal’ validity and I am no exception.
My partner and I lived in Greenwich for nearly a decade and I suppose that
place has a significance for me. J. S. Mill lived in Blackheath, near the gates
to Greenwich park, and the Royal Observatory is a kind of shrine to our
understanding of the physical universe. We have also lived near the oldest Newcomen beam engine in the world. That is a powerful symbol of
both modernity and the injustices of class inequality.
How would you
describe your own writing?
I aim to combine academic rigor with a lightness of touch and, I hope, total
clarity. I suspect I don’t manage to live up to any of these goals!
Are there certain
themes that draw you to them when you are writing?
I’m quite obsessed with certain themes. How free are we? Can we overcome
prejudice? Can we reach a consensus about values?
Tell us about how you
approach your writing. Are you a planner or a pantser?
I plan everything I write. Writing an article is a bit like I imagine it
feels to conduct an orchestra. You have lots of interconnected themes and you
have to try to fuse them into a harmonious whole. There are times when I feel I
am doing it but nothing is ever really satisfactory.
Where do you get
your ideas from?
A great range of places including news and current affairs as well as
drama. Science fiction is a good way to place characters in situations which
highlight the kinds of debates that interest me. We might wonder, for example,
if AI can be classed as living and as having rights (I’m skeptical about the
idea that we are anywhere close to producing machines with artificial
consciousness, even if they show apparent problem solving abilities).
My relationship with narrative is a complex one.
Obviously, fiction can ‘enlarge the circle of concern’ ( as the Philosopher
Perter Singer calls it) by asking us to imagine how the world looks from the
point of view of others. On the other hand, stories are often driven by the
divisions created between heroes and villains, or ‘us’ and ‘them’. Our cultural
stories are often a way of creating a kind of group solidarity, and stories
about nation and ethnic identity can be especially toxic in these respects.
They say that successful writers need to be selfish. How far do you agree with this?
I guess that all our interests compete for our attention and that includes writing. Perhaps it is a paradox but I feel my own work is both an exercise in self-discovery (perhaps even self-creation) and one of communication. I think the urge to know ourselves and to be known to others is a part of the motivation of many writers. To say writing is a selfish activity is probably unfair in the sense that walking in the countryside could also be said to be selfish and yet few would begrudge us the space for contemplation that walking gives us. Writing gives us the chance to focus but, although done in isolation, it can be a deeply social activity because it involves an attempt to communicate. As far as discipline is concerned, I have the luxury of writing when inspiration strikes. At those times, it is more of a compulsion than a choice.
Beyond your family
and your writing, what other things do you do?
I have been, intermittently, a keen chess player but I would not define
myself as creative in any real sense. I think my principle source of meaning is
in my relationships with others and this includes family members and close
friends. I once talked about a ‘community of choice’ to mark out those we
choose to make part of our lives. I count myself very lucky to know so many
people who enrich my life greatly.
Would you describe
yourself as a ‘cultured’ person?
I enjoy the philosophical questions raised by and in the arts. Theatre
can be hugely thought provoking as can cinema. I’ve given insufficient
attention to questions about what counts as ‘art’ (a key philosophical
question) but reading fiction plays a relatively limited role in my life. I am
sure this is to my detriment.
Are you interested
in history and if so does it impact on your writing?
This is, again, a difficult one for me. The history of ideas is hugely
important for me and an awareness of the processes that have led us to our
current circumstances is too. However, the drive to try to define something
that is, in a sense, true for all times and places makes a certain kind of ‘a
historical’ perspective important to me. Not all philosophical writers take
this line but I am one of those who do.
How did the Covid
pandemic affect you as a writer?
It gave me time to think and raised a whole series of questions about
power and inequality which we need to continue to address. There is a sense
that it also both raised the profile of the state as an essential aspect of our
lives and yet also further undermined our faith in a range of political
institutions. What worries me most is the way that inequality is driving a divisive
kind of popularism which is both intolerant and authoritarian. I think the
pandemic provided a kind of interlude in this trend but might have accentuated
it in some respects.
There is a lot of
talk at the moment about political correctness, about the Woke movement, about
cultural appropriation, about diversity. What are your thoughts on this, with
regard to writing?
There are things I won’t say for the same reasons that all of us, I
hope, hold back from comment. I think we are mostly fairly sensitive to the
feelings of others. Furthermore, I think that free comment has to fall short of
harassment to be legitimate. However, context is very important. I wouldn’t go
out of my way to offend a person of faith for example but, if we are engaged in
a debate, I think it is legitimate to make fairly strident comments about the
absurdity of certain views. I have no objection to being told that a particular
film, let’s say, deals with a distressing theme (my liberty to watch or
otherwise is enhanced by that warning) but the idea that we should be protected
from distress by some kind of censorship is both absurd and dangerous. Young
people, for example, need to know that some people think committing genocide is
a good idea. Again, context matters. I want kids to know things but not to wake
up in the night screaming.
Where would you
place your own work, on a continuum with PURE FANTASY at one end and COMPLETE
REALISM at the other?
I don’t write creative fiction but, to the extent I read fiction at all,
it is often of comic fantasy/sci-fy nature. I really think that people massively
underestimate the power of humour to illuminate truth (philosophy is often about pointing our error and even
absurdity ). The writing of people such as Douglas Adams and Terry Pratchett
are often both funny and laser beam focused on our follies.
If you have
anything else you’d like to tell us, not covered by these questions, feel free
to add it here.
I’ve realized
that accepting that I don’t know certain things is ok. I don’t know what the
relationship is between consciousness and the physical world and I never will. I
don’t know how my brain creates my consciousness or how much reality is
dependent on our observation of it. I don’t know what caused the first event to
happen, given that all events have causes. I also realise that I have far less
freedom than we often imagine ourselves to have. I occasionally ask my students
to what extent we choose our own personalities. Of course, we don’t and we are
all the products of the interaction between nature and nurture. If we are lucky,
we get to have pretty good frontal cortex development (and good impulse
control) but while some might find such thoughts depressing I find they make me
more forgiving of myself and others. Knowing that there is nothing you’ve done
to deserve the hand you got dealt is a great antidote to prejudice. It is also
the core idea in the work of Rawls.
******
Thank you very much, Phil, for a brilliant and fascinating showcase.
******
In March, I will be showcasing
another of the fabulous 20-20 Club writers:
Glen Lee
Not to be missed!
Wow. Fantastic fascinating insight into Philip's work Lou. His paper is complex but very readable and understandable. Very clear. Thank you both. xxxx
ReplyDeleteThanks for reading. Philip says to pass on his thanks too.
DeleteWelcome. Philip is a wise, thoughtful, considerate person. xxxx
ReplyDeleteGood, reading, as usual. Is there no end to your talents? Your paintings are really very good. As to your bathroom, it's like the Savoy's compared to mine.
ReplyDelete